Case argued today before Supreme Court could devastate public sector unions
Mandatory union dues, the lifeblood of public sector unions, are challenged.
The Supreme Court’s 2016 schedule begins this morning with oral arguments in a dispute over public union dues. In Friedrichs v. California Teachers Association the Court is asked to strike down two rules that that artificially prop-up public sector unions.
First, the Plaintiff challenges a California statute imposing “agency shop agreements” under which non-union members must nevertheless pay the union for its collective bargaining services.
Second, Plaintiffs seek to reverse California law that requires all employees to pay the union for non-bargaining activities unless they opt out each year, asking that the burden be reversed to require annual opt-ins for those who wish to contribute.
Both challenges are brought under the 1st Amendment’s implied freedom of association, as incorporated to the states through the 14th Amendment.
Background
Friedrichs is the latest in a 40-year series of cases challenging agreements that require non-members of union that have exclusive bargaining rights to contribute to the union anyway, and the statutes that allow or compel such agreements.
The current rule is from the Supreme Court’s decision in Abood v. Detroit Board of Education, 431 U.S. 209 (1977). In Abood and a companion case, teachers argued that the agency shop agreement in their teacher’s union contract violated their 1st Amendment rights by requiring them to “associate” with the union and its speech in the form of mandatory dues. The operative complaint in the companion noted the union was engaged:
in a number and variety of activities and programs which are economic, political, professional, scientific and religious in nature of which Plaintiffs do not approve, and in which they will have no voice, and which are not and will not be collective bargaining activities.
431 U.S. at 213. Thus the core issue in Abood was that the employees did not want to contribute to causes with which they did not agree, but were compelled to do so by operation of state law.
The Supreme Court’s decision in Abood discusses two earlier cases in depth: Railway Employees Department v. Hanson, 351 U.S. 225 (1956) and Machinists v. Street, 367 U.S. 740 (1961). According to the Abood Court:
The record in Hanson contained no evidence that union dues were used to force ideological conformity or otherwise to impair the free expression of employees, and the Court noted that, “[i]f assessments’ are in fact imposed for purposes not germane to collective bargaining, a different problem would be presented.” Ibid. (footnote omitted). But the Court squarely held that “the requirement for financial support of the collective bargaining agency by all who receive the benefits of its work . . . does not violate . . . the First . . . Amendmen[t].” Id., at 238.
431 U.S. at 219. Hanson thus stands for the proposition that compelled contributions to collective bargaining and related expenses is permissible. Five years later, in Street:
the record contained findings that the union treasury to which all employees were required to contribute had been used “to finance the campaigns of candidates for federal and state offices whom [the plaintiffs] opposed, and to promote the propagation of political and economic doctrines, concepts and ideologies with which [they] disagreed.” 367 U.S. at 744.
The Court recognized, Id., at 749, that these findings presented constitutional “questions of the utmost gravity” not decided in Hanson. . .
431 U.S. at 219-20. The Street court went on to hold that requiring workers to contribute to union speech violated the National Labor Relations Act, thereby dodging the constitutional question. Nevertheless, the language of the decision is clear enough that required contributions to non-collective bargaining activities are unlikely to survive judicial scrutiny.
So, after Hanson and Street, agency shop agreements’ constitutional status was that they could compel workers to contribute to union collective bargaining, and compelled contributions to union campaigning had not been deemed a constitutional violation only because the Court was able to find a statutory dodge. Hanson and Street, however, did not involve public unions.
Public/Private Divergence
Abood incorporated Hanson’s endorsement of compelled contributions to collective bargaining into the public union context. A public union is a union of government employees, as opposed to a union of workers in the private sector. The plaintiff teachers in Abood made two arguments for treating public unions differently from private unions for purposes of analyzing an agency shop agreement. As the Court framed it:
First, the appellants note that it is government employment that is involved here, thus directly implicating constitutional guarantees, in contrast to the private employment that was the subject of the Hanson and Street decisions. Second, the appellants say that, in the public sector, collective bargaining itself is inherently “political,” and that to require them to give financial support to it is to require the “ideological conformity” that the Court expressly found absent in the Hanson case.
431 U.S. at 226. The Court summarily rejected the first argument, noting that the agency shop agreement is either compelled or allowed by statute for public and private unions alike, so any putative harm to reluctant members is a product of government action in either case. As such, precedent from Hanson and Street applied notwithstanding the distinction.
The Court treated second argument with more substance. The contention that collective bargaining is inherently political:
rests upon the important and often-noted differences in the nature of collective bargaining in the public and private sectors. A public employer, unlike his private counterpart, is not guided by the profit motive and constrained by the normal operation of the market. Municipal services are typically not priced, and where they are they tend to be regarded as in some sense “essential,” and therefore are often price-inelastic. Although a public employer, like a private one, will wish to keep costs down, he lacks an important discipline against agreeing to increases in labor costs that in a market system would require price increases. A public sector union is correspondingly less concerned that high prices due to costly wage demands will decrease output and hence employment.
The government officials making decisions as the public “employer” are less likely to act as a cohesive unit than are managers in private industry, in part because different levels of public authority — department managers, budgetary officials, and legislative bodies — are involved, and in part because each official may respond to a distinctive political constituency. And the ease of negotiating a final agreement with the union may be severely limited by statutory restrictions, by the need for the approval of a higher executive authority or a legislative body, or by the commitment of budgetary decisions of critical importance to others.
Finally, decision making by a public employer is, above all, a political process. The officials who represent the public employer are ultimately responsible to the electorate, which, for this purpose, can be viewed as comprising three overlapping classes of voters — taxpayers, users of particular government services, and government employees. Through exercise of their political influence as part of the electorate, the employees have the opportunity to affect the decisions of government representatives who sit on the other side of the bargaining table. Whether these representatives accede to a union’s demands will depend upon a blend of political ingredients, including community sentiment about unionism generally and the involved union in particular, the degree of taxpayer resistance, and the views of voters as to the importance of the service involved and the relation between the demands and the quality of service. It is surely arguable, however, that permitting public employees to unionize and a union to bargain as their exclusive representative gives the employees more influence in the decisionmaking process than is possessed by employees similarly organized in the private sector.
431 U.S. at 227-29 (emphasis added). The Court then denied these acknowledged and inherent political dimensions to public union collective bargaining had any relevance to whether contributing to such collective bargaining violated employees’ constitutional rights:
The very real differences between exclusive agent collective bargaining in the public and private sectors are not such as to work any greater infringement upon the First Amendment interests of public employees. A public employee who believes that a union representing him is urging a course that is unwise as a matter of public policy is not barred from expressing his viewpoint. Besides voting in accordance with his convictions, every public employee is largely free to express his views, in public or private, orally or in writing. . . .
The differences between public and private sector collective bargaining simply do not translate into differences in First Amendment rights. Even those commentators most acutely aware of the distinctive nature of public sector bargaining and most seriously concerned with its policy implications agree that “[t]he union security issue in the public sector . . . is fundamentally the same issue . . . as in the private sector. . . . No special dimension results from the fact that a union represents public, rather than private, employees.”
431 U.S. at 230-32 (Citation omitted.) The Court therefore held that the rule from Hanson and Street that allowed compelled contributions to “collective bargaining, contract administration, and grievance adjustment purposes” applied to the public union context as well.
The Court then confirmed the suspicion from Street that compelled contributions to a public union’s campaigning activities violated employees’ First Amendment right of free association. The key:
is the proposition that a government may not require an individual to relinquish rights guaranteed him by the First Amendment as a condition of public employment. The appellants argue that they fall within the protection of these cases because they have been prohibited not from actively associating, but rather from refusing to associate. They specifically argue that they may constitutionally prevent the Union’s spending a part of their required service fees to contribute to political candidates and to express political views unrelated to its duties as exclusive bargaining representative.
431 U.S. at 234 (citations omitted). The Court agreed:
We do not hold that a union cannot constitutionally spend funds for the expression of political views, on behalf of political candidates, or toward the advancement of other ideological causes not germane to its duties as collective bargaining representative. Rather, the Constitution requires only that such expenditures be financed from charges, dues, or assessments paid by employees who do not object to advancing those ideas and who are not coerced into doing so against their will by the threat of loss of governmental employment.
431 U.S. at 235-36. Summarizing the decision, the Abood Court wrote:
To compel employees financially to support their collective bargaining representative has an impact upon their First Amendment interests. An employee may very well have ideological objections to a wide variety of activities undertaken by the union in its role as exclusive representative. His moral or religious views about the desirability of abortion may not square with the union’s policy in negotiating a medical benefits plan. One individual might disagree with a union policy of negotiating limits on the right to strike, believing that to be the road to serfdom for the working class, while another might have economic or political objections to unionism itself. An employee might object to the union’s wage policy because it violates guidelines designed to limit inflation, or might object to the union’s seeking a clause in the collective bargaining agreement proscribing racial discrimination. The examples could be multiplied. To be required to help finance the union as a collective bargaining agent might well be thought, therefore, to interfere in some way with an employee’s freedom to associate for the advancement of ideas, or to refrain from doing so, as he sees fit. But the judgment clearly made in Hanson and Street is that such interference as exists is constitutionally justified by the legislative assessment of the important contribution of the union shop to the system of labor relations established by Congress.
431 U.S. at 222. Read that last line again: “the judgment clearly made in Hanson and Street is that such interference as exists is constitutionally justified by the legislative assessment of the important contribution of the union shop to the system of labor relations established by Congress.”
In other words, the Court deferred to Congress’s determination that collective bargaining and the union’s ability to conduct collective bargaining effectively are worth some amount of impinging on workers’ First Amendment rights.
Is Abood a Dead Law Walking?
Abood has many problems, and appears poised for reversal. In the first place, Friedrichs is all but indistinguishable from Abood. A group of teachers argue that they should not be required to contribute to the public union at all, including both for collective bargaining and for anything else. This is not an instance where won of the parties is trying to carve out a nitsche, exception or nuance, but a direct attack on the continued viability of the rule itself. In their Brief For The Petitioners, the plaintiff teachers explicitly ask that Abood be overturned in their:
The logic and reasoning of this Court’s decisions have shattered the legal foundation of its approval of such compulsion in Abood v. Detroit Board of Education, 431 U.S. 209 (1977) — a decision that was questionable from the start, as Justice Powell argued persuasively in his separate opinion. Id. at 245 (Powell, J., concurring in the judgment) (describing the majority’s opinion as “unsupported by either precedent or reason”). The Court should now discard that jurisprudential outlier.
This frontal assault is why Friedrichs poses such a threat to unions and union supporters. Just the fact that the Court agreed to hear the case is an ominous sign, since the Court does not take cases without either a significant and new issue, or a substantive chance of changing current law. The Supreme Court’s website notes that the Court receives about 10,000 petitions for a writ of certiorari (requests that the Court hear a case on its discretion) per year, and accepts 75-80, or just .8%.
In addition, decisions in recent public union cases have been increasingly skeptical. Just two years ago in Harris v. Quinn, the Court intimated that Abood was on shakey ground. According to Dr. John Eastman of Chapman University’s Fowler School of Law and the Claremont Institute’s Center for Constitutional Jurisprudence:
Harris v. Quinn has at least made Abood a ghoul, one of the walking dead. At issue was whether in-home care givers could be compelled to contribute to the public employee union coffers – the annual amount in Illinois is about $3.6 million! – merely because they were paid out of state Medicaid funds (made available because Illinois found it much more cost effective to pay for in-home care than to pay for care in a medical facility). By the same five-to-four line-up that divided over the First Amendment language in Knox, the Harris Court held that Abood could not be expanded to cover not just “full-fledged public employees” but also those who are “deemed to be public employees solely for the purpose of unionization and the collection of an agency fee.” And in the process, the Court hammered another big nail in the coffin of Abood, calling its “analysis questionable on several grounds,” including some that “have become more evident or troubling in the years since” Abood was decided. . . .
“A union’s status as exclusive bargaining agent and the right to collect an agency fee from non-members are not inextricably linked,” noted the Court. Moreover, a compulsory “agency-fee provision cannot be sustained unless the cited benefits for personal assistants could not have been achieved if the union had been required to depend for funding on the dues paid by those personal assistants who chose to join,” and “[n]o such showing has been made.” These two statements cut right to the heart of arguments that have previously been relied upon to uphold compulsory union dues. The ghoul is left crawling along on stubs.
Richard A. Epstein (Senior Fellow at the Hoover Institution and Professor of Law at NYU) takes it the next step, writing that the union is not only unable to make a showing that it can achieve its goals from willing donors alone, but that the union is affirmatively destructive to some employees. Prof. Epstein writes:
[some employees] correctly perceive that they are worse off with union representation. Thus excellent teachers often favor merit raises. They oppose seniority preferences that tie wages and job protection to years of service. They bridle under rules that give weak or incompetent teachers outsized protection against dismissal. Yet these unhappy teachers cannot quit because they know that all other public school systems are burdened with similar rules. It is therefore perfectly sensible for them to prefer no union at all to one that gives them union representation free of charge.
(Emphasis in the original.) Professor Epstein’s preferred outcome in Friedrichs (and presumably Professor Eastman’s as well), is as weighty as it is simple:
In an ideal world, the Supreme Court would use Friedrichs to dismantle mandatory collective bargaining root and branch. But short of that, what the Court should do, and do unanimously, is set dissenting workers free from union domination by striking down all agency shop provisions.
I do not see the Court unwinding mandatory collective bargaining altogether. At least not in Friedrichs, where it is so unnecessary to the outcome.
Instead, I expect the Court to hold that mandatory contributions to a public union by non-members of the collective bargaining unit are unconstitutional. Whether such mandatory contributions are viable in private-sector unions and whether mandatory collective bargaining itself pass muster will wait for case more on point.
Donations tax deductible
to the full extent allowed by law.
Comments
The best decision would be that public sector unions are unconstitutional. That would make everything else moot.
Wrong.
The basic civil right of free association makes that impossible.
But there’s nothing that says a public-sector union should be allowed to bargain collectively. Until Kennedy, Federal employees were not, though they could join a union
There’s nothing in the constitution requiring the government to consent to collective bargaining with its employees. But there’s nothing prohibiting it either, so it’s not open to the court to strike it down. That’s Congress’s job, if it can muster the numbers for it.
On what possible grounds could the court decide that?
On the contrary, freedom of association would seem make banning such unions unconstitutional.
The purpose of any union is (allegedly) to benefit it’s members at the expense of the employer and the employer’s customers. In the case of public-sector unions, the employer and the customers are one and the same – the people of the city/county/state/United States. Public-sector unions are therefore detrimental to the people and should be abolished.
Wrong.
Weak
Specify. In detail.
There’s a union model (trades, for instance) where union members are “value-added” workers because they’re trained better than non-union workers.
As a free market guy, I’m cool with that…so long as unions enjoy no special treatment in law or regulation. Which they DO.
Put them on equal footing in the marketplace, and let employers decide on merit.
That was fine back in the days when unions had apprenticeship programs, and they could virtually guarantee a well-trained group. Today, all they do is collect dues, and sign on more and more members for that purpose. Look in the halls of outfits like the IBEW or the Longshorman’s Unions. The halls are packed with men looking for work, yet, the union signs up more and more every day.
But that’s total bullshit, Griz. The trade unions still DO have apprentice programs AND continuing training programs.
IF they were signing on MORE members, you’d see them expanding. They aren’t.
If they’re “value added” then they don’t need to be a union; they could get the same premium on their labor in individual bargaining. It would be like professional certification, which attracts a premium on its own merit.
Unions extract a premium for their members not by offering extra value, but by violence and the threat of violence. That is and has always been their principal tool, and it’s become so entrenched that nowadays they hardly ever need to actually use violence, or even to openly threaten it, because the threat is so well understood.
It depends on what the union’s “non-collective bargaining activities” are.
Some unions, usually trade unions, also provide no-cost or reduced-cost job training and job placement (or re-placement) services for their members, thus building a “higher-value” workforce for the employer. When the union helps provide training, union employees will tend to be better-trained. That’s in addition to collective bargaining, and I’d argue is an equally valid use of membership dues, but sadly, not many unions do this anymore.
Most unions who make headlines, though, are as you say: “collective bargaining” equates to “give us what we want or we’ll strike (and if we’re longshoremen, we’ll break s#!t, too)!” Such strong-arm, thuggish tactics do not provide positive optics, but they don’t seem to care; they have the numbers (via mandatory membership) to back it up.
Lazy moochers. They want the benefits of labor unions’ struggle for higher pay and better benefits and working conditions, but do not want to pay for it.
Wrong.
*Look, I can do it too!!*
No, they simply want their union to represent their interests. If they cannot opt out, they cannot require the union to represent them properly.
Unions do nothing for safety conditions. Liability leery insurance companies do.
Exactly, so I say if they don’t pay dues, the wages and benefits bargained for by the union should not apply to them. Let them negotiate their own terms and see how generous the benefits and salary they get are!
The trouble with that is when you don’t have the option to not pay dues.
My workplace union engages in activities unrelated to collective bargaining that I wholeheartedly disagree with, but membership dues are mandatory for all employees, members and non-members alike. I’m literally paying for them to campaign politically, espousing views I find misguided at best and abhorrent at worst, but short of quitting I have no way to opt out.
That is what’s at issue in this case.
Why on earth do you imagine they would get worse deals than the union did? On the contrary, often they can get better deals, but union rules prohibit it.
It would be nice if the union quit digging its grubby paw into my pocket every paycheck. It would also be nice if employees had to opt in. The fact that unions prefer opt out shows you what lazy bums they are. If the unions were so great, people would be looking to sign on the dotted line and happily fork over dues for all the union “benefits.” Instead, union membership is spiraling ever downwards, and unions depend upon the life support of forced dues to keep on lumbering along, old dinosaurs that they are.
This is the key to the current case:
“…[some employees] correctly perceive that they are worse off with union representation. Thus excellent teachers often favor merit raises. They oppose seniority preferences that tie wages and job protection to years of service. They bridle under rules that give weak or incompetent teachers outsized protection against dismissal. Yet these unhappy teachers cannot quit because they know that all other public school systems are burdened with similar rules. It is therefore perfectly sensible for them to prefer no union at all to one that gives them union representation free of charge. ”
For several years running, there was chaos in school systems. The California Legislature had placed very strict requirements on how the school systems must spend most of their money with respect to various well-intended programs tied to outside contractors. The only real control the systems had was over pay for teachers (i.e., numbers of teachers), and they were then required to cut their budgets. The teachers’ union argued that such cuts must be made on the basis of strict seniority, without regard to quality of teaching. They won.
The teacher’s union predictably won this point, possibly because they pay a substantial fraction of the cost for local elections.
The result was that the school districts persistently issued pink slips to competent, younger teachers, for several years running, but were forced to retain teachers who were demonstrably less productive.
The local parents have not been happy, and they can name names.
The process through the US Supreme Court may be slow, and is reminiscent of the dismantlement of the “Separate but Equal” theory, which eventually fell because it did not work in practice.
That system would be great if firing and lay offs were done strictly by merit, but we all know that is not how it works in the real world. In the real world administrators favorites get job offers while hard working excellent teachers get sent packing because they aren’t ‘in the click’. This goes on in every non union place I have ever worked. The union way may not be the best way but it eliminates favoritism, which is what it was designed to do.
That is bullsh*t. In the real world, wherever there is no union interference, merit is exactly how it works, because there’s no reason for it to work any other way. And even in your fantasy world, why does someone who’s been there longer deserve more than someone who’s managed to suck up to an adminstrator? What’s so great about simply sticking around because they weren’t able to get rid of you? Why should that entitle you to anything?
Forcing people to either join a union and pay the dues or allowing them to not join and still pay the dues is a form of tyranny. It is not free association for those who have to pay dues or not have a job in that industry. It is not a benefit to have union thugs badger people into a slight majority vote to get the shop to go union. That is tyranny. When it comes down to it, it is the union which benefits the most from union activity and the members are paying the price.
Unions have a habit of getting in bed with the wrong people whether it’s the mafia or politicians, but I repeat myself.
Mr. Levin, terrific post. Thanks
The “life-blood” of public sector unions is also the life-blood of the Democrat Party.
Look what happened in Indiana, Wisconsin, and other states that ended state collection of union dues out of paychecks – union membership collapsed by 75% – 90%, depending on the union, within a few years. Political contributions from those unions dropped even more (bosses still going to pay themselves first, and that expense doesn’t change).